Don’t Blame “Paganism” for the United States’ Problems

On December 25th, 2023, The Atlantic published an op-ed by David Wolpe, a prominent American rabbi, titled “The Return of the Pagans.” In the op-ed, Wolpe asserts that both the political left and right in the United States have embraced fundamentally “pagan” ideas about the world (by which he means ideas derived from and characteristic of the traditional non-monotheistic religions of the ancient Mediterranean, particularly Greece and Rome) and that this supposed “pagan” influence is the cause of many of the problems that the United States faces today.

For those who don’t know, I’m a graduate student in Ancient Greek and Roman Studies and my main research focus is ancient Greek religion. Given this interest, I was quite intrigued to see an article published in a major news outlet with a title proclaiming that “paganism” has returned. Sadly, I soon found that Wolpe’s idea of “paganism” is a wildly inaccurate caricature that has more to do with nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophies than with the non-monotheistic religions of the ancient Mediterranean world. The op-ed got under my skin, so I decided to let it furnish an opportunity to educate interested readers about what ancient polytheistic religions were like—and, just as importantly, what they weren’t like.

Why “pagan” is a misnomer

Let me make one fact clear from the beginning: no one in ancient times ever identified themself as a “pagan.” In the first place, the ancient Greeks and Romans did not have a word for or concept of “religion” as a distinct domain of human thought and activity. For them, dealing with the gods and other supernatural powers was simply an intrinsic part of life. They certainly had no name for the specific “religion” that they themselves practiced or a name for a practitioner of that religion distinct from a practitioner of a different religion.

Without going into too much detail, the concept of “religion” as a distinct category of human activity is not a natural or universal one. On the contrary, it first arose in the specific historical and cultural context of early modern Europe as the result of specific cultural and social forces. No one in the ancient Mediterranean world shared this concept.

From very early on, Christian authors writing in the Latin language described themselves metaphorically as milites Christi, which means “soldiers of Christ.” In Roman military slang, paganus was a pejorative word for “civilian,” which connoted inferiority and lack of discipline. By around the middle of the fourth century CE, following the metaphor of Christians as “soldiers of Christ,” Christian authors writing in the Latin language adopted the word paganus as a pejorative label for anyone who was not Christian. The word paganus, in turn, has given us the contemporary English word pagan.

For most of its history, the term pagan has been a pejorative, an insult, or a slur. It is only in modern times that people who identify in association with the ancient pre-Christian religious traditions of Europe and the Mediterranean have begun to reclaim it as one of self-identification.

Using the term “pagan” to describe people who practiced non-monotheistic religious traditions in ancient times before Christianity became the dominant religion of the Mediterranean world is inherently misleading because it implicitly affirms the Christian perspective, which sees all religions other than Christianity as fundamentally the same. In reality, these religious traditions were quite disparate in many ways; the only essential feature they all have in common is that Christianity ultimately supplanted all of them as the dominant religion in the lands where they were practiced.

On top of this, for many modern readers, the term pagan is loaded with all kinds of negative stereotypes. For many people, the term immediately evokes connotations of falseness, backwardness, primitiveness, and savagery that less explicitly ideologically loaded, more descriptive terms like “ancient Greek religion” generally do not.

Despite this, because Wolpe uses the term pagan extensively throughout his essay, I will reluctantly use the term in this response. I want to be absolutely clear, though, that, when I use it, I do so recognizing that it is a deeply problematic and not particularly useful term for understanding religions of the ancient world.

“Paganism” and the role of the gods in human morality

One of the central claims of Wolpe’s op-ed is that “pagan belief systems” center around the self and are not concerned with human morality. He writes in his second paragraph:

“Most ancient pagan belief systems were built around ritual and magic, coercive practices intended to achieve a beneficial result. They centered the self. The revolutionary contribution of monotheism was its insistence that the principal concern of God is, instead, how people treat one another.”

This description is partly correct as it applies to the polytheistic religions of the ancient Mediterranean world, but it includes a dire misunderstanding that leads Wolpe astray throughout the rest of his piece. I will start with what it gets right and then address where it goes horribly wrong.

It is true that most people in the ancient Mediterranean world did not regard their gods as morally perfect, nor did they see them as role models of moral behavior whom humans should strive to emulate. They did not regard their gods as all-loving or all-benevolent.

They did not worship the deities because they loved the deities or even necessarily because they believed that the deities were morally deserving of worship, but rather because they believed that the deities were extremely powerful and that it was in their own best interest to appease them, which they believed they could accomplish through worship.

The foundational principle on which ancient Greek and Roman religions—and most religions of the ancient Mediterranean region in general—operated was that of reciprocity. People believed that, if they did something to please a particular deity or group of deities, then that deity or group of deities might give them something that they asked for in exchange. This principle is often summarized with the Latin phrase “Do ut des,” which means “I give so that you may give.”

ABOVE: Tondo from an Attic red-figure kylix dating between c. 510 and c. 500 BCE, depicting two men sacrificing a pig to Demeter

It is true that, in general, most Greeks and Romans at least did not believe that the deities were concerned with policing ordinary humans’ everyday thoughts and behavior. As far as they were concerned, the deities were above that stuff; they didn’t believe that the gods care whether someone looks at another person with lust in their heart or masturbates. Wolpe, however, makes a dire mistake in assuming that this means that “pagan” belief systems are fundamentally selfish and do not regard “how people treat one another” as important.

Contrary to Wolpe’s assertions, the Greeks and Romans did very much believe that the gods would directly punish humans who committed certain kinds of particularly heinous crimes. In fact, Greek myths and literature are full of stories in which deities punish humans for various crimes and even punish entire cities and nations for tolerating such crimes.

For instance, the Greeks knew that a deity was sure to punish anyone who mistreated one of their own priests or other earthly representatives. This idea occurs already in one of the oldest surviving works of ancient Greek literature: the Iliad, an epic poem set during the Trojan War which developed from oral tradition and probably came to exist in something resembling the form we know today sometime around the second quarter of the seventh century BCE or thereabouts.

In the opening scene of the epic, Chryses, the Trojan priest of the god Apollon, begs the Achaian (i.e., Greek) commander Agamemnon to return his daughter Chryseïs, whom the Achaians have captured and whom Agamemnon has taken as his own sex slave, and offers to pay a ransom for her return. Agamemnon scornfully rejects Chryses’s plea, so Chryses prays to Apollon to punish the Achaians. In response, Apollon rains down arrows of plague upon the Achaian army. Thus, the very opening chapter of Greek literature is one of divine punishment.

Similarly, the Greeks knew that a deity was bound to punish anyone who wronged a person who sought protection at the deity’s altar or cult statue. Famously, myth holds that, during the Achaian sack of Troy, the Trojan princess Kassandra embraced the cult statue in the temple of Athena on the Trojan akropolis and explicitly invoked the right of sanctuary. The Achaian warrior Aias the Lesser, however, forcibly dragged her away from the cult statue and raped her in Athena’s temple.

In response to this atrocious crime and act of sacrilege, Athena ordered the Achaians through the seer Kalchas to put Aias the Lesser to death. When the Achaians left without killing him, she convinced her father Zeus to send a storm upon their fleet, which scattered their ships and sank many of them.

ABOVE: Tondo from an Attic red-figure kylix by the Kodros Painter, dating to between c. 440 and c. 430 BCE, depicting Aias the Lesser dragging the Trojan princess Kassandra away from Athena’s cult statue

One of the most sacred principles in Greek religion was ξενία (xenía), which refers to the sacred and divinely protected relationship between a host and a guest. The Greeks and Romans believed that it was against sacred law for a host to mistreat a guest or a guest to mistreat a host and that the gods were certain to punish any host or guest who did so.

Xenía is a central theme in the Odyssey, another early Greek epic poem, which probably came to exist in something resembling the form in which we know it today sometime around the middle of the seventh century BCE. In the poem, Odysseus, the king of the island of Ithaka, has been gone from his home for twenty years and, in his absence, a whole host of suitors seeking the hand of his wife Penelope have taken over his house; they never leave, they torment Penelope, plot to murder Odysseus’s son Telemachos, abuse his slaves, and are eating up all his livestock.

In Book 22 of the epic, the climax of the poem, the goddess Athena helps Odysseus, Telemachos, and two loyal slaves (the swineherd Eumaios and the cowherd Philoitios) to massacre the suitors in a brutal mass slaughter. This massacre of the suitors comes as a divinely ordained punishment for their lack of xenía.

ABOVE: Photo from Wikimedia Commons showing Side A of a Campanian red-figure bell-krater by the Ixion Painter dating to around 330 BCE depicting Odysseus, Telemachos, and Eumaios slaughtering the suitors of Penelope

Another kind of crime that the Greeks believed the gods were certain to punish was ὕβρις (hýbris), which is a term that can refer to basically any extreme or unwarranted act of insolence, aggression, violence, or sacrilege that a person commits out of pride or an inflated sense of self-importance and that is degrading to its victim. Acts that could conceivably be described as hýbris include everything from boasting that one is superior to the gods, to slapping a man across the face in front of a large crowd to humiliate him, to abusing a corpse, to committing mass genocide.

The ancient Greeks also believed that the gods were certain to punish anyone who killed one of their own blood relatives. In Aischylos’s tragedy The Libation Bearers, first performed at the City Dionysia in Athens in 458 BCE, Apollon commands the protagonist Orestes to kill his mother Klytaimnestra as retribution for her having murdered her husband (Orestes’s father) Agamemnon. In The Eumenides, performed as part of the same trilogy, the Erinyes, chthonic goddesses who torment those who have killed their own blood relatives, torment Orestes for having killed his mother, so Apollon and Athena arrange a trial for Orestes.

Sophokles’s tragedy Oidipous Tyrannos, which was first performed at the City Dionysia in Athens around 429 BCE, begins with the god Apollon sending a plague upon the city of Thebes, which he will only lift when the city finds and punishes the man who murdered Laios, the previous king.

By the end of the play, it turns out that the murderer is none other than Oidipous, the current king, that Laios was Oidipous’s own father, and that Oidipous has also unknowingly married his own mother Iokaste and fathered children by her. Iokaste hangs herself and Oidipous gouges out his own eyes with her dress pins and is exiled from the city forever.

ABOVE: Oidipous and Antigone, painted in 1842 by the French Academic painter Charles Jalabert

This, however, brings us to the second problem with Wolpe’s notion that “paganism” is not concerned with “how people treat each other,” which is that, quite simply, for at least some ancient Greeks, it was not the gods’ place to dictate what is moral or immoral, but rather the place of humans to discover using reason.

In the Athenian philosopher Plato’s dialogue Euthyphron, which he wrote sometime in the first half of the fourth century BCE, Socrates meets a prophet named Euthyphron who is prosecuting his own father in court for the murder of a hired servant because he believes that the gods demand it. Socrates then proceeds to question Euthyphron, pointing out that saying that a god commands something does not bring one closer to understanding whether it is morally good, since this simply raises the question of whether a thing is good because it pleases the deity or it pleases the deity because it is good.

If one says that a thing is pious because it pleases a deity, then one lacks a consistent definition of piety, because different deities could disagree about whether an act is pious or about the extent to which it is. If, on the other hand, one says that a thing pleases a deity because it is pious in itself, then one is still left with the question of what actually makes the action pious. In other words, Socrates shows that one cannot define moral goodness simply by its relation to the gods.

ABOVE: Photograph from Wikimedia Commons of a marble head of the Athenian philosopher Socrates on display in the Naples Archaeological Museum

“Paganism” and class

Another central claim of Wolpe’s op-ed that the true ultimate object of worship in “paganism” is power and that “paganism” therefore encourages humans to pursue the relentless acquisition of power, wealth, and status. The op-ed begins with this paragraph:

“Take a close look at Donald Trump—the lavishness of his homes, the buildings emblazoned with his name and adorned with gold accoutrements, his insistent ego, even the degree of obeisance he evokes among his followers—and, despite the fervent support he receives from many evangelical Christians, it’s hard to avoid concluding that there’s something a little pagan about the man. Or consider Elon Musk. With his drive to conquer space to expand the human empire, his flirtation with anti-Semitic tropes, his 10 children with three different women, Musk embodies the wealth worship and ideological imperialism of ego that are more than a little pagan too.”

It becomes clear from Wolpe’s statements later in the article that he derives this notion of “wealth worship” as a “pagan” value from his reading of the German existential philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche (lived 1844 – 1900), who based his ideas about “pagan” values on his reading of ancient Greek and Roman literary texts.

ABOVE: Photograph of the nineteenth-century German existential philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche, from whom Wolpe derives many of his notions about “paganism”

Nietzsche rightly observed that the surviving ancient literary texts written in the Greek and Latin languages by followers of traditional polytheistic religions frequently glorify wealth and power, while Jewish and early Christian texts are more frequently critical of these attributes. This, however, is not due to a fundamental difference between “pagan” and monotheistic attitudes toward wealth and power, but rather due to the nature of the texts that have survived, the specific social situations of the authors who wrote them, and the audiences whom they originally addressed.

The vast majority of the surviving ancient literary texts in the Greek and Latin languages were produced by educated, upper-class Greek and Roman men whose privileged backgrounds fundamentally shaped their worldviews and who regarded educated, upper-class Greek and Roman men like themselves as their primary audience. These authors, however, represent only of a small, highly privileged subset of all the people who practiced traditional polytheistic religions in antiquity.

The vast majority of people in the ancient Mediterranean who worshipped “pagan” gods were not upper-class Greek and Roman men. We can be quite certain that enslaved people, non-elite free people, women, and people who were not ethnically Greek or Roman had ideas about religion and the social order that differed from those of the elite men who produced most of the surviving literary texts. The perspectives of these groups, however, are obscured by the fact that very little writing from them has survived.

Even some of the surviving literary texts produced by elite men, however, critique the aristocratic ideology. Notably, the Athenian tragic playwright Euripides (lived c. 480 – c. 406 BCE) incorporates explicit critiques of this ideology into some of his tragedies. For instance, in his tragedy Elektra, which was first performed in Athens in the mid-410s BCE, Euripides portrays Elektra, the daughter of King Agamemnon of Argos, as having been forced against her will to marry a destitute peasant of undistinguished lineage, who treats her with great honor, even though she resents his poverty.

When Elektra’s brother Orestes arrives in return from a long exile, he initially mistakes his own sister for an enslaved woman (El. 107–111) and she, in turn, mistakes him for a criminal (El. 216–219). These misidentifications undermine the traditional Greek aristocratic notion that it is possible to tell whether someone is of noble birth by their physical beauty.

When Orestes meets his sister’s husband, the revelation that he is honorable, but poor, prompts Orestes to give the following speech (El. 367–385) about how wealth, poverty, and skill in battle are all useless metrics for assessing whether a person is really good or bad, since the wealthy are just as likely to be wicked as the poor:

“φεῦ:
οὐκ ἔστ᾽ ἀκριβὲς οὐδὲν εἰς εὐανδρίαν:
ἔχουσι γὰρ ταραγμὸν αἱ φύσεις βροτῶν.
ἤδη γὰρ εἶδον ἄνδρα γενναίου πατρὸς
τὸ μηδὲν ὄντα, χρηστά τ᾽ ἐκ κακῶν τέκνα,
λιμόν τ᾽ ἐν ἀνδρὸς πλουσίου φρονήματι,
γνώμην τε μεγάλην ἐν πένητι σώματι.
πῶς οὖν τις αὐτὰ διαλαβὼν ὀρθῶς κρινεῖ;
πλούτῳ; πονηρῷ τἄρα χρήσεται κριτῇ.
ἢ τοῖς ἔχουσι μηδέν; ἀλλ᾽ ἔχει νόσον
πενία, διδάσκει δ᾽ ἄνδρα τῇ χρείᾳ κακόν.
ἀλλ᾽ εἰς ὅπλ᾽ ἔλθω; τίς δὲ πρὸς λόγχην βλέπων
μάρτυς γένοιτ᾽ ἂν ὅστις ἐστὶν ἁγαθός;
κράτιστον εἰκῇ ταῦτ᾽ ἐᾶν ἀφειμένα.
οὗτος γὰρ ἁνὴρ οὔτ᾽ ἐν Ἀργείοις μέγας
οὔτ᾽ αὖ δοκήσει δωμάτων ὠγκωμένος,
ἐν τοῖς δὲ πολλοῖς ὤν, ἄριστος ηὑρέθη.
οὐ μὴ ἀφρονήσεθ᾽, οἳ κενῶν δοξασμάτων
πλήρεις πλανᾶσθε, τῇ δ᾽ ὁμιλίᾳ βροτοὺς
κρινεῖτε καὶ τοῖς ἤθεσιν τοὺς εὐγενεῖς;”

This means, in my own translation directly from the Greek:

“Alas!
There is no exactitude regarding goodness in men;
for the natures of mortals hold haphazardness.
For already I’ve seen a man of a worthy father
who was nothing and good sons of bad fathers,
hunger in the mind of a wealthy man,
great wisdom in the body of a pauper.
How, then, distinguishing these things, does one judge correctly?
By wealth? That’s a useless and evil judge.
Or by those who have nothing? But poverty holds sickness
and it teaches a man to be wicked through need.
Should I go to skill with weapons? But who, looking down a spearpoint,
could be a witness of the sort who is good?
It is better to give up these things in vain.
For this man is a neither great among the Argives
nor is he puffed up about his house;
even though he’s one of the masses, he’s found to be the best.
Don’t be foolish; men wander around full
of worthless notions. Judge mortals by their company
and the well-born by their characters.”

Although Orestes does not realize it, his own actions later in the play become a perfect example of how those of noble birth can behave wickedly. In Euripides’s portrayal, Elektra and Orestes both come across as classist, bloodthirsty, merciless, and greedy to regain the wealth, power, and status that they feel is their right by birth. First, Orestes brutally murders Aigisthos. Then, together, the two siblings brutally murder their own mother Klytaimnestra, whom Euripides portrays much more sympathetically than Aischylos or Sophokles; in this version, she acts kindly toward Elektra and desperately pleads her children to spare her, but they refuse to show any mercy.

ABOVE: Photo from Wikimedia Commons showing Side A of a Lucanian red-figure pelike by the Choephoroi Painter dating to between c. 380 and c. 370 BCE depicting a scene of Elektra and Orestes at the tomb of Agamemnon

In contrast to most Greek and Roman literary texts, which were written by elite men of the dominant culture for a primary audience of other elite men of the same culture, many of the later texts of the Hebrew Bible, all the texts of the New Testament, and all the texts of early Rabbinic Judaism (including the Mishnah and Gemara) were produced by people of marginalized ethnic and religious backgrounds living under foreign occupation.

The Christian gospels describe Jesus—their primary subject, whose reported words make up a large portion of their content—as a Jewish itinerant preacher who came from a family of craftsmen in the tiny village of Nazareth in Galilee (which, for most of his lifetime, was ruled by Herodes Antipas, a client king for Rome) and who preached primarily to poor and working-class Jews.

The apostle Paul, although privileged in the sense that he was an educated man who was literate in Greek and held Roman citizenship, was nonetheless marginalized as a Jew and follower of the Jesus movement under Roman rule. The authors of the gospels themselves were at the very least followers of the Jesus movement and may have considered themselves Jewish.

In the first three centuries CE, Christianity saw its greatest spread among the non-elite (i.e., working and middle) classes in cities in the Roman Empire. Thus, the majority of Christians who used the texts that became the New Testament were not upper-class.

This situation changed in the fourth century CE after Constantine I and his successors began to support and sponsor Christianity. Although some aristocrats held out against Christianity and remained staunch pagans even into the fifth century CE, imperial sponsorship of Christianity made many aristocrats feel that it was more to their advantage to adopt the new religion than to resist it.

As soon as powerful and wealthy people began to be Christians, they devised strategies for rationalizing and explaining away the New Testament’s critiques of power and wealth. As the church itself became wealthy under imperial sponsorship in the fourth, fifth, and sixth centuries CE, it came to employ such strategies as well. (For those who are interested to learn more, the most authoritative academic study of Christianity’s complicated relationship with wealth in late antiquity is Peter Brown’s Through the Eye of a Needle: Wealth, the Fall of Rome, and the Making of Christianity in the West, 350-550 AD.)

Over the past millennium and a half at least, Christian churches and individuals have extracted and hoarded immense material wealth. The Roman Catholic Church is one of the single wealthiest institutions on the face of the planet and has been so for centuries. When one visits Vatican City, all one sees is the church’s unfathomable wealth on full, ostentatious display.

ABOVE: Photo from Wikimedia Commons showing St. Peter’s Baldachin inside St. Peter’s Basilica in Vatican City, with the walls and ceiling encrusted with gold

Thus, Wolpe misunderstands a difference in the nature of our sources as a fundamental difference between “paganism” and monotheism. Unfortunately, these misunderstandings grow even worse; he also fundamentally misunderstands even the Greek and Roman aristocratic ideology that he takes as representative of “pagan” morality.

Most societies of the ancient Mediterranean world were agrarian and pre-capitalist. In any given society, the majority of the population was primarily occupied with agriculture. The primary source of wealth was the ownership of agriculturally viable land and the resources needed to cultivate that land. Although some degree of social mobility certainly existed in ancient societies and it existed to a greater degree in some societies during certain historical periods than others, in general, social hierarchies tended to be fairly rigid.

Most wealthy ancient Greeks and Romans were not capitalist entrepreneurs who actively sought to increase their wealth, but rather old-money aristocrats who derived their wealth from the fact that their parents owned and passed down to them large properties of agriculturally viable land, along with large numbers of enslaved people who worked that land.

In general, these aristocrats were strongly conservative in the sense that they generally opposed any change to the status quo of the society in which they lived and they disdained anyone who actively sought to acquire significantly greater capital than what they had inherited by birth. This disdain extended not only to people born of the lower classes who sought to climb the social ladder, but even to fellow aristocrats who sought to become richer than they already were by birth. Thus, ancient Greek and Roman aristocratic ideologies vehemently opposed the kind of profit-minded entrepreneurship that modern capitalism glorifies.

Class in ancient Mediterranean world was, of course, tied to material wealth, but it often had a lot more to do with who a person’s ancestors and relatives were, what kind of upbringing and education they possessed, what kinds of political and religious offices they held or had connection to, and what public services they or other members of their family had performed.

Thus, the aristocrats of ancient Greece and Rome were far more like the landed gentry of early modern Britain or (perhaps even more) the plantation-owning aristocrats of the Antebellum South than Donald Trump or Elon Musk. In fact, in many ways, Trump and Musk represent everything that ancient Greek and Roman aristocrats looked down on and opposed.

One of the most important values in ancient Greek society and among the Greek aristocracy in particular was σωφροσύνη (sōphrosýnē), which means “moderation” or self-restraint. This meant restraining one’s natural desires, including desires for sex, wealth, food, and alcohol. Greek normative morality held that such pleasures were good in moderation, but seeking or using them in excess was wrong and potentially even dangerous.

The Greeks summarized this principle using the maxim “μηδὲν ἄγαν,” which means “Nothing in excess.” This maxim was of such great importance in Greek religious thought that it was inscribed at the entrance to the Temple of Apollon at Delphoi, which was one of the most important temples in the Greek world.

I have already argued in this blog post I wrote in April 2020 that many ancient Greeks would most likely regard Trump’s lavish and excessive lifestyle as evidence that he lacks sōphrosýnē. I suspect that they would have a very similar opinion of Musk. Indeed, one could even make a compelling case that some of Trump and Musk’s acts of self-aggrandizement qualify as outright hýbris by an ancient Greek definition.

In fact, there is a certain irony in the fact that Trump’s gold-encrusted apartments draw inspiration from the Baroque ornamentation of Christian churches. If you want to know where Trump derives his love of all things that glitter, the answer lies at least as much with the Vatican as it does with anything pagan.

ABOVE: Photograph from Wikimedia Commons of President Donald Trump and Prime Minister Shinzo Abe of Japan in Trump’s gold-encrusted penthouse at Trump Tower

Trump and Musk, however, are not the only people whom Wolpe criticizes for wealth worship. Later in the op-ed, he writes:

“The current worship of wealth is a pagan excrescence. I am spending this year at Harvard, and it is not easy to find an undergraduate who isn’t interested in ‘finance.’ The poets want to go into finance. The history students are studying investment.”

What Wolpe describes in this paragraph is a shift in upper-class ideology that has nothing to do with religion and is, ironically, actually a turn away from the ideology of ancient Greek and Roman aristocrats.

To a significant extent, higher education, particularly at an elite institution like Harvard, has always been about wealth and status. From roughly the Classical Period onward, παιδεία (paideía)—which refers to education in Greek culture, including Greek language, literature, history, art, and philosophy—was considered the defining feature of a well-heeled Greek gentleman that set him apart from those of inferior classes. The Romans likewise considered what we would now call a humanities education the defining feature of a true noble.

For them, a key part of the value of an education in languages, literature, history, art, and philosophy lay precisely in the fact that only a man who was wealthy enough that he had lots of spare time to study, who could afford to buy lots of expensive scrolls, and who could afford to pay expensive tuition for a teacher or private tutor could afford to study them. Thus, for elite ancient Greeks and Romans, education itself was a way of showing off one’s inherited wealth and status.

For the majority, if not the entirety, of Harvard’s existence, the primary value of a Harvard diploma has been as a marker of status and prestige. At least at the undergraduate level, the quality of education at Harvard is not vastly superior to the quality at many state flagship universities, which offer mostly the same subjects and have many talented and dedicated professors. Whether someone learned how to conduct experiments, do calculus, or read Ancient Greek at Harvard or at a public university, they’ve learned essentially the same skill.

Nonetheless, a degree from Harvard confers a boasting privilege on its holder that a degree from, say, IU Bloomington (my own alma mater and a perfectly respectable state university) does not. This boasting privilege rests not on the education one has received itself, but rather on the Harvard name and its associations. Having a degree from Harvard signals to everyone that one is a member of the elite class, which automatically makes most people take them more seriously, regardless of whether they actually deserve to be taken more seriously.

Now, though, capitalism has effected a shift in how people think about education. In reality, under twenty-first-century capitalism, it is nearly or absolutely impossible for a person who was actually born in poverty to attain great wealth, most people who are wealthy now were born to great privilege, and attaining wealth frequently has more to do with having access to necessary resources when starting out and being ruthlessly willing to exploit others than actual talent and hard work. Even so, capitalism justifies the perpetuation of its own existence through the lie that people become wealthy through “merit.”

Thus, capitalism encourages people to see education not as a way of signaling one’s inherited wealth and status in the manner of ancient Greek aristocrats, but rather as training for how to make money and become rich. This leads to a shift in the kind of education that status-minded young people seek out. Specifically, it encourages students to pursue majors that they perceive as oriented toward the future acquisition of greater wealth.

Thus, when Wolpe complains about poets studying finance and history students studying investment, he fails to recognize that studying any subject at Harvard or another elite private university is always to some degree about money and power—either showcasing the money and power that one already has or seeking ways to make more of it.

ABOVE: Photo I took of Memorial Hall at Harvard University when I visited Harvard’s campus on October 8th, 2023

“Paganism” and beauty

Wolpe goes on to claim that “paganism” venerates the beauty of the physical body just as it venerates wealth, writing:

“This worship of the body—of beauty, which is another form of power—is a pagan inheritance. The monotheistic faiths did not disdain beauty, but it was not an ideal they extolled. Not only do biblical heroes rarely merit a physical description, but even traditionally heroic attributes are portrayed as worthless if they lack a spiritual foundation. In the Bible, if someone is physically imposing, that usually signals trouble. Samson is a boor who redeems himself at the last minute. Saul stands a head above the crowd, but is an utter failure as king. The English critic Matthew Arnold famously said that the Greeks believed in the holiness of beauty, and the Hebrews believed in the beauty of holiness.”

It is true that ancient Greek aristocratic ideology extolled physical beauty and held that outward beauty was an indicator of both noble status and inner goodness. Greek aristocrats believed that aristocrats like them tended to be more physically beautiful, morally better, braver, more intelligent, and closer to the gods than people of inferior birth. Because of this, they called themselves καλοὶ κἀγαθοί (kaloì kagathoí), which literally means “the beautiful and good.”

This ideology associating beauty with wealth, status, and moral goodness, however, was far from universally accepted. Even some of the earliest surviving fragments of Greek literature push back against it. For instance, the lyric poet Archilochos (lived c. 680 – c. 645 BCE), who is one of the earliest authors in the Greek language for whom any work at all survives, declares in a fragment that he doesn’t want to serve a general who looks beautiful, but rather one who is brave and does his job well (fr. 60 Campbell = 114 Loeb):

“οὐ φιλέω μέγαν στρατηγὸν οὐδὲ διαπεπλιγμένον
οὐδὲ βοστρύχοισι γαῦρον οὐδ᾽ ὑπεξυρημένον,
ἀλλά μοι σμικρός τις εἴη καὶ περὶ κνήμας ἰδεῖν
ῥοικός, ἀσφαλ εώ ς βεβηκὼς ποσσι, καρδίης πλέως.”

This means (in my own translation):

“I love neither a tall general nor a swaggering one,
nor one exulting in curls, nor one who is shaven,
but rather let me have one who is short and crooked to see between the knees,
who walks with sturdy feet and is full of courage.”

Centuries later, in the fourth century BCE, Plato discussed the difference between outer and inner beauty in one of his most famous and widely studied philosophical dialogues, the Symposion. In the dialogue, the speaker Alkibiades delivers a speech in which he praises Socrates by comparing him to the satyr Marsyas (Sym. 215a–217a). He declares that, like a satyr, Socrates is outwardly physically ugly, but, in the same way that a satyr can entrance his audience by playing the aulos (a kind of double-reeded woodwind instrument), Socrates holds the power to entrance listeners with the beauty of his words.

Alkibiades then goes on to contrast Socrates’s outward ugliness with his inner beauty, saying (Sym. 216d–217a):

“ἔνδοθεν δὲ ἀνοιχθεὶς πόσης οἴεσθε γέμει, ὦ ἄνδρες συμπόται, σωφροσύνης; ἴστε ὅτι οὔτε εἴ τις καλός ἐστι μέλει αὐτῷ οὐδέν, ἀλλὰ καταφρονεῖ τοσοῦτον ὅσον οὐδ᾽ ἂν εἷς οἰηθείη, οὔτ᾽ εἴ τις πλούσιος, οὔτ᾽ εἰ ἄλλην τινὰ τιμὴν ἔχων τῶν ὑπὸ πλήθους μακαριζομένων: ἡγεῖται δὲ πάντα ταῦτα τὰ κτήματα οὐδενὸς ἄξια καὶ ἡμᾶς οὐδὲν εἶναι—λέγω ὑμῖν—εἰρωνευόμενος δὲ καὶ παίζων πάντα τὸν βίον πρὸς τοὺς ἀνθρώπους διατελεῖ. σπουδάσαντος δὲ αὐτοῦ καὶ ἀνοιχθέντος οὐκ οἶδα εἴ τις ἑώρακεν τὰ ἐντὸς ἀγάλματα: ἀλλ᾽ ἐγὼ ἤδη ποτ᾽ εἶδον, καί μοι ἔδοξεν οὕτω θεῖα καὶ χρυσᾶ εἶναι καὶ πάγκαλα καὶ θαυμαστά, ὥστε ποιητέον εἶναι ἔμβραχυ ὅτι κελεύοι Σωκράτης.”

This means:

“But, if you were to open him up from within, you would conclude that he is full of such sōphrosýnē, o drinking companions! Know that he does not care at all whether someone is beautiful, but rather disdains it so much that you cannot imagine, nor does he care whether someone is wealthy or has any other honor that is praised by the multitude. He regards all these possessions as worthy of nothing and not of us—I say to you. And, feigning ignorance and playing like a child, he converses with human beings all his life. I do not know if anyone else has found his inner delights while he is earnest and open, but I saw them at that time and they seemed to me so divine, golden, all-beautiful, and miraculous that I needed to do right away whatever Socrates commanded.”

This idea of true, inner beauty as distinct from outward physical appearance became central to later “pagan” Greek and Roman philosophies influenced by Plato.

Texts like these make it abundantly clear that “pagan” ancient Greeks did not universally accept the equation of physical beauty with goodness.

ABOVE: Painting made by the German Academic painter Anselm Feuerbach in 1869 depicting the drunken Alkibiades’s crashing of Agathon’s drinking party described in Plato Symposion

Later in his op-ed, Wolpe blames the influence of ancient “pagan” worship of physical beauty for a whole host of contemporary cultural problems:

“The veneration of physical beauty, the Instagramization of culture, is pagan to its roots. The overwhelming cascade of drugs, surgeries, and procedures intended to enhance one’s physical appearance—all precursors to ‘designer babies’—is a tribute to the externalization of our values. Movements of hypermasculinity, championed figures such as the now-indicted Andrew Tate, flow from the elevation of the human body to idolatrous status.”

Many humans throughout history, including “pagans,” Jews, and Christians, have sought to alter or enhance their physical appearances through various means. The desire to be outwardly beautiful according to a particular standard is not a specifically “pagan” one. In fact, I will be somewhat controversial and say that it isn’t always necessarily a bad thing. It becomes a problem only when specific unrealistic standards of beauty become so influential or pervasive that those who cannot match those standards feel shamed or alienated by them.

As for what Wolpe says about “movements of hypermasculinity” (by which he means the so-called “manosphere” and those associated with it), it is certainly true that forms of toxic masculinity and misogyny were pervasive throughout many ancient “pagan” societies, including ancient Greece and Rome.

It is also true that present-day “manosphere” movements often draw conscious inspiration from ancient Greek and Roman cultures (or at least their own warped perceptions of those cultures). In fact, the classicist Donna Zuckerberg wrote a book about how these movements draw inspiration from classical antiquity titled Not All Dead White Men: Classics and Misogyny in the Digital Age, which was published by Harvard University Press in 2018.

Despite these facts, toxic masculinity and misogyny are far from uniquely or characteristically “pagan” attributes. On the contrary, throughout history, these forces have been just as pervasive and influential in Jewish, Christian, and Muslim societies as they have been in “pagan” societies. The New Testament and the writings of the Christian Church Fathers contain passages that are just as misogynistic as anything in “pagan” Greek or Roman literature (e.g., 1 Corinthians 14:34–35, 1 Timothy 2:11–15, or Tertullian’s On the Apparel of Women).

Although classicists don’t talk about it nearly as much, contemporary misogynistic movements frequently draw at least as much or more inspiration from historical Christian misogyny as from historical “pagan” misogyny. Indeed, because Christianity is a far more influential a cultural factor in the United States than ancient polytheistic religions, Christianity tends to exert greater influence on contemporary misogyny and toxic masculinity.

Andrew Tate, whom Wolpe expressly mentions, doesn’t identify as a “pagan” and has done little to publicly associate himself with paganism. Instead, he was raised a Christian, he strongly publicly identified as a Christian for a period of several months in 2022, and, since October 2022, he has publicly identified as a Muslim. Although Tate’s understanding of and actual belief in the tenets of either Christianity or Islam is questionable at best and he certainly does not follow Islamic teachings on sex or substance use, his decision to publicly affiliate himself with these Abrahamic religions, rather than “paganism,” is significant.

Finally, although normative ancient Greek conceptions of masculinity bore some features in common with contemporary ones, they also differed in striking ways. For instance, the concept of sōphrosýnē was absolutely integral to the normative Greek conception of masculinity, whereas, at least in the U.S., contemporary conceptions of masculinity tend not to see moderation as an essential feature of manliness. The practice of pederasty was also widely practiced and accepted among ancient Greek men and was seen as a normal part of Greek masculinity, whereas today it very much is not.

ABOVE: Tondo from an Attic red-figure kylix by the Briseïs Painter dated to c. 480 BCE, showing an erastes (the young adult male partner in a pederastic relationship) kissing an eromenos (the adolescent boy partner)

“Paganism” and humility

Wolpe declares:

“The virtue that falls furthest in the pagan pantheon of traits is humility. In the ancient Greek epics, humility is not even reckoned a virtue.”

Wolpe is correct in a strict sense that ancient Greek epics like the Iliad and the Odyssey do not express the concept of humility as a virtue. They do, however, treat the opposite of humility—excessive pride—as a serious vice. Indeed, as I have already addressed, Greek myth and literature treat hýbris, the misdeed that arises from excessive pride, as one of the worst of all misdeeds. Moreover, although ancient Greek religious and philosophical traditions were not concerned with humility per se, they were greatly concerned with the importance of accurate self-perception.

I have already mentioned that the maxim “μηδὲν ἄγαν” (“Nothing in excess”) was inscribed at the entrance to the Temple of Apollon at Delphoi, but there was another maxim that was also inscribed at the entrance to the same temple that was, if anything, even more important: “γνῶθι σεαυτόν” (gnôthi seautón), which means “Know yourself.”

This maxim carried various meanings and interpretations in antiquity, but one of the most important of them was the sense of knowing one’s place, having an accurate awareness of one’s own weaknesses, not being overly proud or haughty, and not thinking that one is above human norms.

In addition, the fifth-century CE Greek anthologist Ioannes Stobaios preserves a list of 147 maxims that were allegedly inscribed somewhere at Delphoi in addition to the more famous ones that were inscribed at the entrance to the Temple of Apollon. Multiple maxims included on this list emphasize the importance of recognizing one’s status as human and, with it, one’s own fallibility and mortality: “φρόνει θνητά” (“Remember you are mortal”) and “εὖ πάσχε ὡς θνητός” (“Fare well as a mortal”).

I would actually argue that the ancient Greek notion of the importance of accurately knowing oneself, including one’s weaknesses and faults, holds greater nuance and is more valuable for life in the modern world than the Christian notion of humility as an inherent virtue.

Quite simply, holding a persistent, inaccurately low opinion of oneself is just as mentally unhealthy as holding an unduly inflated one, and underestimating one’s own abilities or importance can lead to just as serious problems for a person as overestimating them. If someone has the ability to do something, but they do not believe that they do, then they usually will not try to do it and will consequently miss out on opportunities that they otherwise could have taken. It is better to try to hold an accurate awareness of oneself that recognizes both one’s flaws and one’s strengths than it is to be always humble.

ABOVE: Photo I took myself in summer 2023 of the ruined Temple of Apollon at Delphoi from the front, where the maxim “γνῶθι σεαυτόν” (“Know yourself”) is said to have been inscribed

“Paganism” and the place of humans in the cosmos

Wolpe concludes his op-ed by claiming that “paganism” differs from the monotheistic traditions of Judaism and Christianity because monotheism sees humans as God’s special creations made in his own image and subject to his supreme authority, whereas “paganism” sees humans as either virtual gods or mere base animals and, in either case, does not recognize humans as being bound by any moral authority. He writes:

“Should we see human beings as virtual supermen, free to flout any convention, to pursue power at any cost, to accumulate wealth without regard for consequence or its use? Are gold toilets and private rocket ships our final statement of significance? Or is it a system of belief that considers human beings all synapse and no soul, an outgrowth of the animal world and in no way able to rise above the evolutionary mosaic of which everything from the salmon to sage is a piece?”

This is all complete nonsense with absolutely no basis in any ancient evidence. Contrary to Wolpe’s assertions, one of the most central ideas in ancient Greek religious thought was the unique position of humans in the cosmos as neither deities nor animals. I will address both of the positions Wolpe attacks in turn, beginning with the first.

Humans as “virtual supermen”

As I have already touched on above, ancient Greek religion was quite emphatic that humans must remember that we are not gods, that we are mortal, and that we are all doomed to die. The Greeks considered hýbris not just a vice, but an appalling crime that threatened the entire social order.

It is true that, in some cases, ancient Greek religion did allow somewhat more permeable boundaries between humans and gods than monotheistic religions do today. In particular, the Greeks did believe that a very tiny number of humans with extraordinarily great abilities who performed deeds of exceptionally great impact while they were alive could, after their deaths, become a kind of supernatural being known as a ἥρως (hḗrōs; plural: ἥρωες [hḗrōes]), who retained the ability to influence the affairs of the living for better or worse.

The Greeks sought to bargain with and appease these hḗrōes through local hero cults, which in many ways resembled cults of the major deities, only they were more limited in scope and confined to a particular locale.

For the ancient Greeks, whether someone became a hḗrōs after their death had nothing to do with the moral quality of their actions and everything to do with the scale or impact of those actions. This does not, however, mean that the Greeks didn’t care about morality or that they believed it was acceptable for someone to go on a killing spree in order to win the chance to become a hḗrōs; it is simply a case of them regarding cultic practices and morality as independent matters. The Greek veneration of hḗrōes stood in tension with the recognition that hḗrōes sometimes behaved contrary to moral norms that humans were generally expected to follow.

In exceptionally rare cases, the Greeks did believe that some human beings (almost always those who had at least one major deity as their parent) could actually become full, Panhellenic deities, as Herakles and the Dioskouroi (i.e., Kastor and Polydeukes, the brothers of Helene of Sparta) are said to have become. The Greeks, however, very much regarded such cases as extremely rare exceptions to the norm.

The notion of humans as “virtual supermen, free to flout any convention, to pursue power at any cost, to accumulate wealth without regard for consequence or its use” is exactly as antithetic to mainstream ancient Greek religious principles as it is to mainstream contemporary Christian or Jewish principles.

ABOVE: Photograph from Wikimedia Commons showing the northwest heroön, or shrine to a hḗrōs, at the site of Sagalassos in the region of Pisidia in Asia Minor

Some readers may wonder where Wolpe is getting this idea from if not from the ancient Greeks. The answer is that, once again, he is getting it from Friedrich Nietzsche. For background, Nietzsche lived at a time in the nineteenth century when the influence of Christianity seemed to be waning and he saw the threat that nihilism (i.e., the belief that existence has no meaning or purpose and that all values are baseless) posed to his contemporaries.

As a solution to the threat of nihilism, Nietzsche proposed that every man should seek to become what he called an Übermensch, which is often translated as “Superman” or “Overman,” who would reject both nihilism and the value systems of others, including what Nietzsche considered the “slave morality” of Christianity and Judaism.

Wolpe, however, fundamentally either misunderstands or misrepresents even Nietzsche’s concept of the Übermensch. Nietzsche did not envision the Übermensch merely as a greedy human who will pursue wealth and power at all costs. Instead, he saw him as an artist-tyrant who will possess such creativity, will, and power that he can create, sustain, and enforce his own system of values.

Although Nietzsche vehemently maintained that the Übermensch is a kind of being who will come in the future and that no human who has lived so far has ever been one or even come close, in his Will to Power 2.380, he does list the names of those whom he considers to be among the greatest humans who have lived so far, selecting them specifically on the basis of traits that he elsewhere predicts will be characteristic of the Übermensch. The list is: “Caesar, also Homer, Aristophanes, Leonardo, Goethe.” Each of these figures is someone who is known in some capacity as a great writer, poet, or artist. Nietzsche, who was trained as a classicist, had a classicist’s idea of greatness.

Nietzsche would most likely regard men like Donald Trump and Elon Musk as utterly banal and the pettiest kind of human. Although both men are certainly powerful, neither of them has ever displayed anything close to the kind of unbridled humanistic creativity that Nietzsche predicts the Übermensch will wield. Instead of being artist-tyrants, they’re all tyrant and no artist.

Additionally, although one could say that Trump and Musk are driven in certain ways, Nietzsche imagined the Übermensch as someone who will be willing to endure great suffering and discomfort to promulgate his own ideals and vision and it is frankly hard to imagine either Trump or Musk being willing to endure any kind of genuine hardship for sake of any ideal, even their own.

Thus, Wolpe takes his own twenty-first-century misunderstanding of a concept from a nineteenth-century German existential philosopher and falsely attributes it to ancient “pagans,” to whom the concept as he understands it would be quite foreign.

ABOVE: Gallery of men whom Nietzsche considered among the greatest ever to have lived (from top left): Julius Caesar, Homer, Aristophanes, Leonardo da Vinci, and Johann Wolfgang von Goethe

Humans as nothing but base animals?

Now let us address that other position that Wolpe attributes to the deleterious influence of “pagan” thought: the idea that humans are no better than or different from non-human animals. In a section of the essay leading to the conclusion, Wolpe maintains that the modern left has embraced this idea and specifically cites the arguments of the moral philosophers Christine M. Korsgaard and Peter Singer as examples.

The problem with this whole section of the essay is that it has absolutely nothing to do with any ancient non-monotheistic religious tradition. Even Wolpe himself doesn’t try to explain how he thinks it is related to anything ancient; he simply asserts that it is “pagan” and leaves the matter to rest.

In reality, the Greeks at least were quite emphatic in their belief that humans are distinct from non-human animals and that it is important for humans to act better than animals. Despite Wolpe’s suppositions to the contrary, most ancient Greeks did in fact believe that a deity made humans as a special and unique creation.

According to the best-known Greek myth for the origin of humans, which is attested in several ancient sources (e.g., Sappho fr. 207, Plato’s Protagoras 320c–322a, and Pseudo-Hyginus’s Fabulae 142), the Titan Prometheus fashioned the first humans from clay and brought them to life. As I previously discussed in this post I wrote four years ago in 2020, this myth closely parallels multiple ancient Near Eastern creation stories, including the ones recorded in the Book of Genesis.

The main influence behind Singer and Korsgaard’s philosophies is not ancient “paganism,” but rather the scientific and philosophical movements of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. The idea that humans are fundamentally animals is an outgrowth Charles Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection, which he proposed in his book On the Origin of Species, published in 1859. Meanwhile, Singer’s moral philosophy is rooted in utilitarianism, an ethical theory that first developed in the late eighteenth century and flourished in the nineteenth century, especially in Britain.

ABOVE: Roman marble relief dating to the third century CE, currently held in the Louvre Museum, depicting the Titan Prometheus molding the first human beings from clay while the goddess Athena watches

Closing thoughts on Greek ideas about the nature of humanity

The brightest of ancient Greek thinkers were fully conscious of both humanity’s brilliance and inner darkness. Of these thinkers, the ancient Athenian tragic playwright Sophokles is among those who reflect most thoughtfully on what it means to be human. In his tragedy Antigone, which was first performed at the City Dionysia in Athens in 441 BCE, the chorus sings (Ant. 334):

“πολλὰ τὰ δεινὰ κοὐδὲν ἀνθρώπου δεινότερον πέλει.”

This means:

“There are many formidable things, but nothing exists more formidable than a human being.”

This line has a double meaning that makes it difficult to translate. As I discuss in this blog post I wrote back in August 2022, the adjective δεινός (deinós) in Greek bears both positive and negative implications. It describes a thing that is awe-inspiring, wonderful, and majestic, but also frightening and at least potentially dangerous. I have chosen to translate it here as “formidable,” because I believe this captures the deliberate ambiguity of Sophokles’s line.

In this passage, the chorus simultaneously reflects on both the genuinely impressive extent of human achievement and the frightening human capacity for destruction, cruelty, and degradation of nature (an issue which Sophokles specifically dwells on later in the same choral ode).

Meanwhile, one of Sophokles’s speakers also declares in a famous fragment (fr. 13):

“ἄνθρωπός ἐστι πνεῦμα καὶ σκιὰ μόνον.”

This means:

“A human being is only a breath and a shadow.”

At first, this fragment may seem to affirm the idea of humans as “all synapse and no soul,” but to take such an interpretation would be to misunderstand the fragment; the word πνεῦμα (pneûma) in Greek means both “breath” and “soul,” so the fragment actually affirms the existence of a soul. It is instead a reflection on the profound fragility and fleetingness of human existence.

Author: Spencer McDaniel

I am a historian mainly interested in ancient Greek cultural and social history. Some of my main historical interests include ancient religion and myth; gender and sexuality; ethnicity; and interactions between Greeks and foreign cultures. I hold a BA in history and classical studies (Ancient Greek and Latin languages and literature), with departmental honors in history, from Indiana University Bloomington (May 2022) and an MA in Ancient Greek and Roman Studies from Brandeis University (May 2024).

41 thoughts on “Don’t Blame “Paganism” for the United States’ Problems”

  1. As always, your case is incisive, exact, and encyclopedic, and always comes round to your central point. let me add this small footnote of a polemic: Where does Wolpe stand with the Kabballah? Without getting into the full case to be made, a basic reading of Plato, Aristotle, and Philo Judaeus go a long way towards suggesting that some foundational aspects of that tradtion have roots in–Paganism!–well, then…

  2. Excellent as usual. I wonder if you’d ever review Dominion by Tom Holland which makes some similar claims (it seems to me) about how supposedly different all the “pagan” values were, saying ours are thoroughly Christian (even now, contra Wolfe). That seems dubious to me, based on the kind of things you cite here.

    1. Tim O’Neill reviewed Holland’s book: https://historyforatheists.com/2020/01/tom-holland-dominion/. IIUC, Holland’s main point is that modern Western thought is deeply shaped by its Christian past, even for those of us who reject Christianity as a personal faith. This really shouldn’t be disturbing to any current skeptic, except those who are being uncritically partisan: whoever first thought them up, we’ve now seen that rights and so on are Really Good Ideas; we don’t need the Bible to back them up.

      From my brief skim of that review just now, it looks like Holland very much acknowledges the debt that early Christian thought owes to pagan philosophy. Which makes Wolpe’s thesis even sillier; I don’t think Holland is his friend.

    2. I disagree with Tom Holland about many things, but I would agree with his main thesis that Christianity has exerted an indelible impact on present-day western norms and values (to the extent that we can speak of such a thing) and that this impact is so pervasive that it influences even those of us who don’t identify as Christian or who consciously reject Christianity.

      That being said, I think that ancient Greek philosophies (especially Platonism and Stoicism) have exerted a far greater impact on Christianity itself than most present-day Christians are willing to acknowledge. Many of the ideas and values that modern Christianity prides itself on really go back to Plato. One can see this in the fact that so many of the values that Wolpe attributes in his op-ed to “monotheism” can be far more accurately attributed to Platonism.

      Additionally, I think that Holland severely downplays the negative aspects and influences of Christianity in favor of the positive. I am far less convinced than he is that the Christian influence on contemporary western values has been a net positive.

  3. Shorter Wolpe: Monotheism good, anything else bad (and pagan). In the end, he’s just another moral scold.
    And yes, he’s just tossing Korsgaard and Singer into his “paganism” blender, when really his quarrel is with Darwin. I haven’t read the the book he cites, but I have read Korsgaard’s _Fellow Creatures_, where she makes a Kantian case for animal rights (and spends a fair bit of time explaining why she thinks Singer’s utilitarian approach is wrong). Calling either argument “pagan” is truly stupid.

  4. The op-ed was so criticized that it has its own section on Wolpe’s personal Wikipedia page.

      1. The version history says it was added on January 10 by “ShelfLife10”, who also added a paragraph on Wolpe’s claims that the Exodus is non-historical (a bit of a controversial claim in his circles, I imagine). The links in Reference 8 are worth following (particularly the one to Religion Dispatches). Modern neo-pagans are seriously pissed off at Wolpe over this.

  5. > Why “pagan” is a misnomer
    Yes, those who Wolpe might call Greek neo-pagans prefer to call themselves “Έλληνες Εθνικοί” (“Greek Ethnics”, see “Ύπατο Συμβούλιο των Ελλήνων Εθνικών” http://www.ysee.gr/index-english.html). They also have a center here in Astoria, New York. Over the years I’ve been to 2 or 3 of their events. I am sure they would be very happy to hear you talking about some ancient Greek Gods one day.

  6. Very interesting to see you examine ancient morality and worldviews (broadly defined) in this way, and I also learned a little more about Nietzschean philosophy! I think you made a good point when you expressed your opinion on the virtue of humility vs ‘nosce te ipsum’.

    It seems to me that a lot of later ancient philosophers, like Stoics and Neoplatonists, had pretty similar opinions to what this Wolpe ascribes to monotheists: criticism of beautification and so on (then again it seems that some devotees of Abrahamic faiths are eager to identify these philosophers with monotheism).

    1. I think Neoplatonism, to some extent, got taken up into early Christian thought — you can see where some of the central ideas (the One, the Forms) can be given a Christian spin. Ditto the Stoic ideal of calmly accepting whatever happens as ordained by God, whether conceived of as the deity of the Bible, or the rational soul of the universe.

      1. I consider Jews like Wolpe to be water-carriers and Useful Fools for Christian conservatives — they lend a patina of tolerant pluralism to what is at heart an intolerant movement.

        1. Conservative Judaism is the name of a denomination and shouldn’t be conflated with being politically conservative. Wolpe has officiated gay marriages against protests of some members of his own congregation. His perspective in this article might be incorrect historically, but nothing about it is particularly supportive of the Christian Right or that he belongs to the conservative political movement.

          In fact, 64% of those who belong to Conservative Judaism (the denomination) lean towards Democrats.

          See: https://www.pewresearch.org/religion/2013/10/01/chapter-6-social-and-political-views/

      2. I’m still not trusting his word.
        As you pointed out in your “The Right’s attack on LGBT people” article, religious fundamentalism is a threat to democracy and I intend to solve it.

        1. It’s hard to call someone that questions the very historicity of Exodus a religious fundamentalist and it’s difficult to characterize someone that so vociferously attacks Trump as part of the “Religious Right”, which at the moment if challenged will call Trump a Cyrus, someone prophesied who is righteous despite not being of the religion.

  7. Fantastic post, thank you Spencer! I saw this article making the rounds on some pagan subreddits, and am happy to see such a thorough and measured response to it.

  8. Do you have any book recommendations for a good introductory survey on Ancient Greek and Roman religion? And a few other secondary books one should read on the topic?

    1. For ancient Greek religion, Walter Burkert’s Greek Religion (Harvard University Press, 1985) is a classic. Although it is somewhat dated at this point and not all parts of it have aged well, it is still a generally good introduction. Jan Bremmer’s Greek Religion (Oxford University Press, 1994) and Jennifer Larson’s Ancient Greek Cults: A Guide (Routledge, 2007) are also excellent. Larson’s book is probably the best recent general introduction.

      If you want to know about religion in Classical Athens specifically, the best general book on the subject is probably Robert Parker’s Athenian Religion: A History (Oxford University Press, 1998). For Greek mystery cults, the best general work is Greek Mysteries: The Archaeology and Ritual of Ancient Greek Secret Cults edited by Michael B. Cosmopoulos (Routledge, 2003). For the role of women in Greek religion, I recommend Barbara Goff’s Citizen Bacchae: Women’s Ritual Practice in Ancient Greece (University of California Press 2004). For the role that ecstatic states of mind played in Greek religion, I recommend Yulia Ustinova’s Divine Mania: Alteration of Consciousness in Ancient Greece (Routledge, 2018).

      For Roman religion, Antonia Tripolitis’s Religions of the Hellenistic-Roman Age (William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 2001) is a good, affordable, undergraduate-level introduction. Jacob L. Mackey’s Belief and Cult: Rethinking Roman Religion (Princeton University Press, 2022) serves as a recent and much-needed corrective to the age-old scholarly assumption that Roman (and Greek) religion was all about practice and that belief played little or no part in the matter.

      I hope these recommendations are helpful! If there are more specific aspects of Greek and Roman religion you are interested in, I probably have recommendations about those as well.

  9. I disagree with you I think Christianity is the foundation I’m a morality not demonstrated only in Holland’s book but the first to condemn slavery unlike the rational Greeks and Romans new atheist Love to worship through justify slavery Christians were the first to condemn slavery here is Gregory of Nyssa What price did you put on rationality? How many obols did you reckon the equivalent of the likeness of God? How many staters did you get for selling the being shaped by God? ‘God said, let us make man in our own image and likeness’ (Gen 1:26). If he is in the likeness of God, and rules the whole earth, and has been granted authority over everything on earth from God, who is his buyer, tell me? Who is his seller?”

    1. I am quite well aware of this passage and I myself have quoted it in several previous blog posts. My point above is that Christianity has had impacts on western society and norms that I would view as both positive and negative and I’m not sure whether the positives outweigh the negatives.

      Regarding the specific issue of slavery, Christianity is far from an inherently anti-slavery religion. No text included in the canonical Christian Bible ever unambiguously condemns slavery as an institution and many texts included in it expressly condone slavery. The majority of Christians in late antiquity regarded slavery as an unfortunate, but natural and inevitable, consequence of humanity’s fall from grace and did not view an individual owning slaves as necessarily evil; Gregory of Nyssa was an unusual exception in this regard.

      In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, most defenders of slavery were just as devout Christians as most abolitionists were and they appealed to the Bible and Christian teachings to justify their position just as much as abolitionists did. The abolitionists were not in any way more authentically Christian than slavery defenders.

      1. I think the question of whether Christian influence is a net positive or negative is unanswerable — better or worse than what? Than how European history would have turned out if the Jesus cult had just died out by 100 CE? There’s no way of knowing that.

  10. I disagree the I will admit the Paul of the pastoral Epistles does seem to be a little more pro slavery but the Paul of the aesthetic epistle seems to be anti encouraging people to take freedom if you can get the chance and even in the pastoral Epistles it condemns people who capture slaves and it encourages them even the quotes that condone it don’t it I’ve looked at them they still encourage people to treat the slaves well and treat them as your brother (1Cor 7:21) Though he adds an enigmatic comment that has been variously interpreted as “although if you can gain your freedom, do so” (NIV) or perhaps “even if you can gain your freedom, make use of your present condition now more than ever” (NRSV and it was unusually pro-woman Paul even encouraging women mostly but some love to use Corinthians 14 but that’s been mistranslated I’ll link to a paper debunking this reading Joseph A. P. Wilson, “Recasting Paul as a Chauvinist within the Western Text-Type Manuscript Tradition: Implications for the Authorship Debate on 1 Corinthians 14.34-35”, Religions, 2022, 13(5), p. 432 heretical Christian works we see a pro woman attitude Gospel of Thomas contains extraordinary passages devoted to what can only be described as women’s ‘liberation’.
    We have seen that the conventional view in antiquity was that women could not be fully rational beings. Their subordination, like that of slaves, was justified in that way. The Gospel of Thomas urges a new project on believers: nothing less than turning women into men! They are to become as ‘one’. By that it is clearly meant that women should be enabled to become rational agents, to recognize that they have the same rational and moral capacities as men. ‘When you make the two into one, and when you make the inner like the outer and the outer like the inner . . . and when you make male and female into a single one, so that the male will not be male nor the female be female, then you will enter (the kingdom).’13 That reconstruction of the self, which Paul had urged on his followers, is here tied overtly to a change in the status of women. The implication of the ​text is that only when women are free can men also be truly free – that the reciprocity which belief in human equality entails is only possible when their shared nature is fully acknowledged Larry Siedentop, Inventing the Individual: The Origins of Western Liberalism ( 5. The Truth Within: Moral Equality

  11. It seems to me that allowing militaristic language and thought into a belief system is always harmful, although Paul nailed it down pretty early with his “Whole Armor of God” passage in Ephesians.

    Spencer, do you have any thoughts on the museum in the UK changing their pronouns for the Roman emperor Elagabalus to she/her in displays? Do you think that’s the best reading of the textual evidence?

  12. I was reading an old commentary by darelbach what Luke is saying is not to hate our family means to love something less r, mother, son, and daughter; while
    Luke mentions father, mother, wife, children, brothers, sisters, and one’s own
    soul. Nothing else is to be first.

    The call to “hate” is not literal but rhetorical (Denney 1909–10).5
    Otherwise, Jesus’ command to love one’s neighbor as oneself as a summation of
    what God desires makes no sense (Luke 10:25–37). The call to hate simply means
    to “love less” (Gen. 29:30–31; Deut. 21:15–17; Judg. 14:16).6
    The image is strong, but it is not a call to be   insensitive or to leave all feeling behind. Marshall (1978: 592)
    suggests “renounce,” which is possible depending on how it is defined (Grundmann
    1963: 302; Michel, TDNT
    4:690–91).7 Following Jesus is to be the disciple’s “first love.”
    This pursuit is to have priority over any family member and one’s own life,
    which means that other concerns are to take second place to following Jesus
    (Luke 8:19–21; 9:59–62; 12:4, 49–53; 16:13). Matthew 10:37–39, Luke 9:24, and
    John 12:25 make a similar point, though Matthew speaks of loving family more,
    rather than hating, thereby softening the remark’s emotive force

  13. Once again, an excellent piece of material that demonstrates “Brandolini’s law.” At one point is just your just asking to yourself, “when is this nonsense going to stop?” Reading through the comments, your statement of: “My point above is that Christianity has had impacts on western society and norms that I would view as both positive and negative and I’m not sure whether the positives outweigh the negatives” is exactly why I do not subscribe to the simplistic portrayal of Christianity as utterly good nor bad, and more fundamentally, reductive essentialization of it. There has never been a “pure” Christianity isolated from outside factors and influences.

    Similar to the Complexity Thesis explained by Tim O’Neill (Again) in his goodreads view of
    The Warfare Between Science and Religion: The Idea that Wouldn’t Die (J. Hardin, R.L. Numbers, R.A. Binzley eds, Johns Hopkins University Press, 2018) :

    “Harrison, like most modern historians of science, accepts the so-called Complexity Thesis of John Hedley Brooke. In his own contribution to this book, Brooke outlines that idea by noting “there is no such thing as the relationship between science and religion”, scorning any simple formulation of either “conflict” or “harmony” as futile – “as if some single magic formula could meet an imagined all-encompassing need”. (p. 265) History simply cannot be reduced to formulae or generalisations of this kind , so while there have indeed been instances of conflict, neither side in them could be said to wholly represent anything we could call “science” or, by the same token, “religion”.”

    As Tim O’Neill notes in his review of Holland’s Dominion: “A true post-Christian can see the oppression, murder, persecution and horror done as a result of Christianity, but can also see the other side of the historical ledger: the beneficial elements that Christianity has given to western culture and, through it, to the modern world generally.” Something that I think all Christians can consider as well!

    Christianity led to same-sex love to become taboo, (in theory, practice paints a much more complex picture) yet at the same time the modern campaign for LGBT rights traces its roots to a broader campaign and struggle against sexism and racism and to moral calls for equality, which ironically, Christianity influenced immensely. Christianity led to the emergence of secularism and the modern nation-state, yet at the same time said modern nation-states with their vast capacity to commit violence, invaded, conquered, enslaved, and colonized vast swathes of the world, fundamentally altering the global landscape to this day. Not to mention violence and warfare committed on a scale unseen up until that point, unbeaten until the days of the killing fields of the 20th century. While states, using the myth of religious violence, thoroughly put the churches of their respective areas to state subjugation, contributing to much intolerance.

    I think your notes on Christianity being heavily influenced by ideas stretching back to Plato is spot-on. The development of our modern values is a highly complex one, one of the most glorious triumphs of multi0-culturalism in history, and is this particular relationship is wonderfully described by Larry Siedentop in his Invention of the Individual, 2014 by “pagan (Pre-Christian) philosophy shaped by centuries of Christian moral intuitions.”

    One of this year’s best articles yet!

  14. It’s an okay response but I will say this secular states are just as violent as religious ones and we already I don’t have to look forward to prove this look at modern-day China or the Soviet Union but the that was atheism but as other studies have demonstrated studies show that the most secular people in Europe tend to be the most intolerant to Muslims

  15. I remember this interesting quote from C. S. Lewis:

    When grave persons express their fear that England is relapsing into Paganism, I am tempted to reply, “Would that she were.” For I do not think it at all likely that we shall ever see Parliament opened by the slaughtering of a garlanded white bull in the House of Lords or Cabinet Ministers leaving sandwiches in Hyde Park as an offering for the Dryads.

  16. I only know one Pagan who said something like “men are nothing but base animals” and that would be the anti-Christian writer Celsus. In a striking passage he claims ants and bees have societies as advanced as humans, talk to each other in their own languages, and that “looking from the perspective of God”, God wouldn’t see a difference. He then goes further and says animals are closer to God and have a clearer image of Him. I was quite enchanted by these words, which remind me much of the modern Gaia-theory types. And I still don’t know if anyone at his time agreed with him.

  17. Good post. Obviously this guy isn’t familiar with ancient Near Eastern religions either.

    Egyptian Solar Religion in the New Kingdom (Routledge, 2012), Jan Assmann:

    “Not only does the mercy of god, which is near the oppressed and listens to the petitioner, express itself in the omnipresence and omniscience of god, but also the justice of god, which proceeds against evil. These two aspects of the saviour and judge, mercy and justice, can scarcely be separated. Justice (Maat) in this context means salvation: the liberation of the oppressed from the hands of his oppressor. In his aspect of “lord of Maat”, god is typically invoked as the helper of the widow and the orphan, the poor and helpless…

    CT 1130 also contains a similar self-justification of god, by expressly emphasising that the creator created the good things of life for all people equally, “but their hearts transgressed against what I ordained”. Evil was not a part of creation. It arose from the will (“heart”) of those who wished to distance themselves from this order…

    A clear statement of the judicial function of the god: he has forbidden wrongdoing and does not allow it to exist. Everyone has to answer to god… Those who act as the husband of the widow, refuge of the oppressed, ferryman of the boatless are acting as the image of god. In light of the idea that man is the image of god, this whole phraseology already acquires theological meaning long before it appears in hymns. It points to the ways in which human beings can realise Maat. By imitation, human beings can thus share in the goodness and justice of a god who sustains and administers his creation as judge and shepherd, nourisher and supporter… Understood in this way “wrongdoing” seems to consist in destroying the divinely created equality of all people, that is, in oppression of the weak (poor) by the strong (rich).”

    Moral Values in Ancient Egypt (University of Zurich, 1997), Miriam Lichtheim:

    “And earlier we had encountered the attitude of forgiveness in the statement of the nomarch Khety (chap. 3): “I answered evil with good.” Any and Amenemope are outstanding in teaching to leave retaliation to the god. For Any I cited “Do not rush to attack your attacker … ” Amenemope goes the whole way to forgiveness in his chapter 2: When the wicked man is foundering in storm and flood, you should rescue him… Egyptians, Mesopotamians, and Israelites, all three had the same approach to retaliation, vengeance, and forgiveness… Altogether, the Egyptian sources indicate a growing admission of human weakness and the need for forgiveness…

    Now, in the fullness of Ramesside modemity, the Instruction of Amenemope drew the portraits of two kinds of evil-doers. One, the “heated man”. He is the quarrelsome, aggressive, and violent person. Several chapters (2-4, 9-10, & 12) describe him and advise how to deal with him: avoid him, do not befriend him. And if exposed to him, keep quiet. He will be destroyed by his own iniquity, as all evil-doers are. Storm and flood will carry him away, unless you take pity on him and save him. It may be that your forgiveness will make him repent (chap. 2). Altogether, the advice to “you” is to cling to the “silent man” who is his opposite. Even worse than the “heated man” is the “greedy man” (chap. 6). He is the oppressor of the weak, and he is everyone’s enemy…

    Understood as being rooted in human nature, grown to maturity during three millennia of recorded practice and discussion, Egyptian ethic possessed an essential rightness because it focused on the basic fact of human interconnectedness, and on the need to make that interconnectedness benefit all segments of the population… Altruism advanced early beyond the reciprocity principle of do ut des by emphasizing the obligation of everyman to care for the poor and disadvantaged, and, altogether, by stressing benevolence toward all… Gradually, belief in a last judgment, and piety, became closely associated with moral thought…

    The increasingly sophisticated outlook on human affairs which evolved in the second and first millennia came to include foreign nations as peoples equally human, and partners in the adventures of individual and national existence. The gods above were thought of as shepherds of all mankind… By the formulation of Coffin Text spell 1130, where the sun-god declares “I made every man like his fellow”, and by later formulations as well, the Egyptian made explicit what was implied in his ever repeated teachings on benevolence to all. He recognized the brotherhood of mankind. By this recognition his ethic was an ethic for everyone.”

    Of God and Gods: Egypt, Israel, and the Rise of Monotheism (University of Wisconsin Press, 2008), Jan Assmann:

    “My next example represents the most conspicuous case of such a transposition in Egyptian religious history. It concerns the rise and the final breakthrough of a religious trend Egyptologists call “Personal Piety.” An individual forms a special relationship with a certain deity, which in Egyptian is paraphrased in formulas such as “putting god N into one’s heart” and “walking (or acting) on the water of god N.” This new trend finds its first expression in prayers and tomb inscriptions of the fifteenth century…

    This new form of Personal Piety is best described as a semantic transposition according to which the concepts and rhetoric of loyalism were transferred from the political to the divine sphere, where they served as a model for the relationship between god and man. God acceded to the role played by Akhenaten in the Amarna period—and, earlier, by the king in the Middle Kingdom and by the patron in the First Intermediate Period—acting as protector for all: father of orphans; husband of widows; refuge for the persecuted; protector of the poor; good shepherd; judge; pilot and steering oar; merciful toward his followers; wrathful toward his enemies. The concept of transposition means that something is withdrawn from one sphere and transferred to another. Thus, protection was no longer sought on the “mundane” plane, from king or patrons, but rather on the divine plane, from a deity.”

    The Parables of Jesus: A Commentary (Eerdmans Publishing, 2000) Arland J. Hultgren:

    “Just as the misfortunes are typical of those that the unfortunates of the world experience, so there are texts that contain lists of typical acts of kindness towards them–and which commend these acts–in various literatures of the world. In the eighth-century-B.C. Akkadian “Counsels of Wisdom” a sage teaches that one should give food, drink, and clothing to those in need. Other literatures include the Egyptian Book Of The Dead (125: A person being judged says, “I have given bread to the hungry, water to the thirsty, clothes to the naked and a boat to him who was boatless”), the Mandaean Ginza (2.36.13-17:”If you see one who hungers, feed him, someone who thirsts, give him to drink; if you see one naked, place a garment on him and clothe him. If you see a prisoner, who is believing and upright, obtain a ransom and free him”), and more…As indicated above, there is nothing particularly Christian about the six works of kindness that those on the right have done; they belong to the world of moral reflection and behavior in various cultures, including those prior to the ministry of Jesus.”

    “Unlike other important deities, Amun does not seem to have been thought of as living in some distant celestial realm. His presence was everywhere, unseen but felt like the wind. His oracles communicated the divine will to humanity. Amun was said to come swiftly to help Egyptian kings on the battlefield or to aid the poor and friendless…

    In spite of this imperfection, the creator was said to have done many things to help humanity. In Coffin Texts 1130, the Lord of All describes his four good deeds. These were to create the four winds to give the breath of life to every body, to make the annual Nile flood so that everyone would get enough food, to create everyone with equal potential, and to make every person’s heart “remember the West.” This last deed implies that from the beginning humans were destined for an eternal life in the Beautiful West, the realm of the dead. A Middle Kingdom text set in the turbulent First Intermediate Period compares humanity with a flock and the (unnamed) creator with the good shepherd who cares for them. “For their sakes He made heaven and earth, and drove away the rapacity of the waters. So that their nostrils should live He made the winds. They are images of Him, come forth from His flesh. For their sakes He rises in heaven. For them He made plants and flocks. . . .”. New Kingdom hymns to the creator god Amun also refer to god making people “in his own image” but are vague about how this was done.”

    1. The last quote starting at “Unlike other important deities, Amun does not seem to have been thought of…” is from Egyptian Mythology: A Guide to the Gods, Goddesses, and Traditions of Ancient Egypt (Oxford University Press, 2004). I forgot to put the source before the quote.

Comments are closed.